If you have ever been interested in researching Japanese philosophy, chances are you have probably skipped through many ''orientalist'', easy-peasy books on the subject and ended up reading either some popular Japanese writers such as D.T.Suzuki or Buddhist Americans such as Alan Watts. People who go on into reading actual modern Japanese philosophy such as the exemplified by the Kyoto School are far, far fewer in number and usually academic types with big glasses and a constant migraine. And people fully breaking into the subject of Japanese political philosophy or its conervailing authors are the finest slice of the pie. This book, edited by Graham Parker and Setsuko Aihara, belongs to the second category. It was published in USA around the nineties, even though its source material comes from diverse lectures and seminaries by prominent philosopher and academic Keiji Nishitani [治谷 啓治] (1900-1990), from 1949 and onwards. He himself was part of the so-called Kyoto School; early 20th century philosophers who happened to be working in the same universities at the time and who did not call themselves by that name. The only glue who ended up grouping them together was the strong metaphysical concern with the notion of 無 [Nothingness], and a certain debt [either strong or tenuous] with the seminal figure of Nishida Kitarō [西田 幾多郎], (1870-1945) and his lifetime work on the subject.


As a young man, I used to carry Thus Spoke Zarathustra around with me wherever I went. It was like my Bible. (...) among things Japanese I liked best Netsume Sosdeki and books like the buddhist talks of Hakuin and Takuan. Through all these many interests, one fundamental concern was constantly at work, I think... In the center of that whirlpool lurked a doubt about the very existence of the self. something like the Buddhist ''Great Doubt''. So it was that I soon started paying attention to Zen

Things in nature are what they are, and do what they do ''without why'' (...) in the realm of natural phenomena, in the midst of the grand cycles of nature, nihilism is not even possible, let alone actual (...) In a city where such a huge population does so much -and so much moving- in the course of a day, and in an environment so distanced from the natural, nihilistic moods are more likely to arise (...) In the ineluctable awareness of the active presence of multitudes of one's fellow human beings devoting their energies toward work and recreation -both as means to survival and distraction- the question of the point of it all is more apt to arise with some force.
Nishitani's analysis of Western nihilism is vastly improved by his deep knowledge of the Buddhist tradition, also deeply rooted on a mistrustboth of both the permanent existence of eternal subtances and the existence of the Ego. For one direct assumption by poor readers of Nietzsche is that his rejection of the metaphysical entails a glorifying of the psychological ''me'' and its desires; this also happens to bad readers of Stirner and his ''egoism''. Nishitani masterfully explains Nietzsche down to his most fundamental standpoint, in which the personal ego is itself dissolved in the body itself and its fundamentally a-rational ground; where fixed personality is itself revealed as an arbitraty generalization from tiny, contradictory, striving bits of lived experience, each one of them as absolute as many others. As he said in the aforementioned quote, both nihilism and Buddhism hold hands on an absolute critique of the self, of personality and eternal essence.
While the first half of the entire work consists on a detailed analysis of Nietzsche's thought, it also includes Bauer, Fehuerbach, Schopenhauer, Fichte, Hegel, and Marx. The next important section deals with Stirner alone, ''Nihilism as Egoism'', comprising his political and philosophical works swiftly and masterfully. The next section goes at large about ''Nihilism in Russia'', with Turgenev and Dostoevsky as prominent figures. Here Nishitani, a well reader of Dostoevsky, is nevertheless skewed towards a literary analysis of nihilism in Russia, leaving behind its vast political and social implications. And this is a quite trademark among the various philosophers of the Kyoto School: they just won't deal with the political and usually prefer a fully metaphysical takedown of, as an example, Marx himself (on grounds of his limited understanding of human nature and its inner universe) rather than addressing his political or economic philosophy. Since the topic at hand is nihilism as such it can be forgiven; but the next author on the list is Heidegger himself, his section being entitled ''Nihilism as Philosophy''. While it constitutes an excellent analysis of the heideggerian standpoint, it could be perceived as problematic; Nishitani's lectures date back from 1950, a decade during which Heidegger recluded himself in the woods and did not renounce his Nazi party membership card. At the time Nishitani's job at the academy had also been frozen by the American administration due to his former participation in the infamous Chūōkōron conference [中央公論], during which he justified Japanese expansionism on grounds of historical necessity and political righteousness, also using some race-charged words (something you have to go around and about to do in Japanese, which does not have abvious, ''easy'' terms to do it unlike most languages]. He also got to visit Heidegger and study with him in Germany, given the fact that Henri Bergson (Nishida's recommendation) was sick at the time. Therefore, the lack of political commentary on Heidegger's philosophy should not be that surprising, since he himself was under sctrutiny on similar grounds, and a personal admiration erased his critiques of Heidegger himself; eventually, Nishitani was able to return to his teaching duties at Kyoto University.
All in all, and ignoring what it does-not-adress, this is a fundamental volume on its subject of inquiry, and one every philosophy student or nihilism-afflicted soul should read at some point in my opinion. Its title alone, ''The Self-Overcoming Of Nihilism'' not only addresses the different strategies adopted by the various historical figures themselves, but also the inner logic of nihilism as such, and its psychological necessity of a breaking point by means of its own logic. Whether it takes the form of an absolute distancing oneself from discourse and reason, recessing to an aesthetic contemplation such as that of Buddhism or Daoism, or the active creation of new provisional values in the face of the falsehood of all earthly authority and order (and here Nishitani brings to mind some mischievous Zen masters), the resolution of nihilism and the means to effectively achieve it are only contained in nihilism itself. Thus the necessity of having it, as Nietzsche states, ''behind onself, beneath oneself, outside of oneself''
While the first half of the entire work consists on a detailed analysis of Nietzsche's thought, it also includes Bauer, Fehuerbach, Schopenhauer, Fichte, Hegel, and Marx. The next important section deals with Stirner alone, ''Nihilism as Egoism'', comprising his political and philosophical works swiftly and masterfully. The next section goes at large about ''Nihilism in Russia'', with Turgenev and Dostoevsky as prominent figures. Here Nishitani, a well reader of Dostoevsky, is nevertheless skewed towards a literary analysis of nihilism in Russia, leaving behind its vast political and social implications. And this is a quite trademark among the various philosophers of the Kyoto School: they just won't deal with the political and usually prefer a fully metaphysical takedown of, as an example, Marx himself (on grounds of his limited understanding of human nature and its inner universe) rather than addressing his political or economic philosophy. Since the topic at hand is nihilism as such it can be forgiven; but the next author on the list is Heidegger himself, his section being entitled ''Nihilism as Philosophy''. While it constitutes an excellent analysis of the heideggerian standpoint, it could be perceived as problematic; Nishitani's lectures date back from 1950, a decade during which Heidegger recluded himself in the woods and did not renounce his Nazi party membership card. At the time Nishitani's job at the academy had also been frozen by the American administration due to his former participation in the infamous Chūōkōron conference [中央公論], during which he justified Japanese expansionism on grounds of historical necessity and political righteousness, also using some race-charged words (something you have to go around and about to do in Japanese, which does not have abvious, ''easy'' terms to do it unlike most languages]. He also got to visit Heidegger and study with him in Germany, given the fact that Henri Bergson (Nishida's recommendation) was sick at the time. Therefore, the lack of political commentary on Heidegger's philosophy should not be that surprising, since he himself was under sctrutiny on similar grounds, and a personal admiration erased his critiques of Heidegger himself; eventually, Nishitani was able to return to his teaching duties at Kyoto University.
All in all, and ignoring what it does-not-adress, this is a fundamental volume on its subject of inquiry, and one every philosophy student or nihilism-afflicted soul should read at some point in my opinion. Its title alone, ''The Self-Overcoming Of Nihilism'' not only addresses the different strategies adopted by the various historical figures themselves, but also the inner logic of nihilism as such, and its psychological necessity of a breaking point by means of its own logic. Whether it takes the form of an absolute distancing oneself from discourse and reason, recessing to an aesthetic contemplation such as that of Buddhism or Daoism, or the active creation of new provisional values in the face of the falsehood of all earthly authority and order (and here Nishitani brings to mind some mischievous Zen masters), the resolution of nihilism and the means to effectively achieve it are only contained in nihilism itself. Thus the necessity of having it, as Nietzsche states, ''behind onself, beneath oneself, outside of oneself''
Comments
Post a Comment